Thursday, June 28, 2018

Philosophy is dead | Review: Changing the Subject by Raymond Geuss

Philosophy is dead

JONATHAN RÉE

Back in the 1970s, Raymond Geuss was a young colleague of Richard Rorty in the mighty philosophy department at Princeton. In some ways they were very different: Rorty was a middle-class New Yorker with a talent for reckless generalization, whereas Geuss was a fastidious scholar-poet from working-class Pennsylvania. But they shared a commitment to left-wing politics, and both of them dissented from the mainstream view of philosophy as a unified discipline advancing majestically towards absolute knowledge. For a while, Rorty and Geuss could bond as the bad boys of Princeton.

The philosophical establishment denounced people like Rorty and Geuss as relativists, bent on destroying the sacred distinction between truth and falsehood. But they defended themselves by pointing out that even if there is such a thing as an almighty final truth, it looks different from diverse points of view, and gets expressed in different words in diverse times and places. They regarded themselves as "perspectivists" or "historicists" rather than relativists, and believed that – to borrow a phrase from Thomas Kuhn – philosophy needed to find a "role for history".

Subscribe to the weekly TLS newsletter

In a beautiful eulogy delivered on the occasion of Rorty's death in 2007, Geuss recalled a conspiratorial moment when his colleague revealed a plan for an undergraduate course called "An alternative history of modern philosophy". Rorty proposed to fill his lectures with supposedly minor characters such as Petrus Ramus, Paracelsus and Johann Gottlieb Fichte, to the exclusion of canonical drones such as Locke, Leibniz and Hume, and out-and-out deplorables such as Descartes (Rorty's pet hate) or Kant (Geuss's). The projected "alternative history" came to nothing. (According to Geuss, Rorty blamed the Princeton "thought police", otherwise known as the Committee on Instruction.) But Geuss's latest book could be seen as a fulfil­ment of Rorty's plan, forty years on.

Changing the Subject is a history of philosophy in twelve thinkers. There are lucid self-contained essays on Socrates, Plato, Lucretius, Augustine, Montaigne, Hobbes, Hegel, Nietzsche, Lukács, Heidegger, Wittgenstein and Adorno; but Descartes, Locke, Leibniz, Hume and Kant don't even make it to the index. The whole performance combines polyglot philological rigour with supple intellectual sympathy, and it is all presented – as Geuss puts it – hilaritatis causa, or in a spirit of fun.

Out of his twelve philosophers, Geuss seems closest to Lucretius, who despised religion (though the word religio meant something rather different at the time), and maintained that the world has no moral purpose and is utterly indifferent to our existence. Hobbes comes almost as high in Geuss's estimation: he invented the concept of the "state" as the locus of political sovereignty, and treated it as an "artificial construct" which pays no regard to such so-called principles as "natural rights" or "the common good". Hegel, as Geuss reads him, was a good disciple of Hobbes because he avoided trying to "justify" the ways of the world, and he opened the way for Nietzsche's furious attacks on self-serving ideas of "truth-telling", "profundity" and "authenticity". In the wake of Lucretius, Hobbes, Hegel and Niet­zsche, philosophy seems to be essentially a battle against the bewitchment of our intelligence by moralistic sentimentality.

There are two different ways of responding to this predicament. Geuss sketches one of them in a scintillating chapter on Theodor Adorno, the twentieth-century aesthete who sought to combine classical Marxism with disdain for the stupidity of the masses. Adorno, you might say, showed signs of intellectual mysophobia, or Platonistic revulsion from impurity, and Geuss – who regards Plato as an "intellectual bully" – is uneasy about Adorno's "relentless negativism". He finds an amiable alternative in Michel de Montaigne who, having no desire to correct the follies of humanity, was "free of all these pathologies".

Geuss pays tribute to Montaigne for never "wagging his finger", but in the end he sides with Adorno. He is a bit of a mysophobe himself, and that seems to be why he never formed a lasting alliance with his old comrade in Princeton. He recalls an occasion when Rorty told him that he found inspiration in the work of Hans-Georg Gadamer, who saw the whole of human existence as a vast "conversation", in which we should try to include everyone, even those with whom we disagree. Geuss tried to convince Rorty that Gadamer was "a reactionary, distended windbag", but Rorty continued on his way: he started to call himself, half-jokingly, a "bourgeois liberal", and began discussing politics in terms of old pieties like "human rights", "democracy", "private life" and even "patriotism". He did not suppose that such phrases had any theoretical justification, but he found them useful for expanding the conversational circle. Geuss, on the other hand, deplored them as "irremediable tosh" and "unwarranted fantasies presenting themselves as irrefutable facts". He was not amused by Rorty's jokes, and found his casualness hard to forgive.

Geuss concludes by suggesting that philosophy is dead: vital signs gave out some forty years ago, he says, and the excitement, creativity and inventiveness of the past have been replaced by dutiful recitations and historical re-enactments. But in this bracing and approachable book he gives himself the lie, demonstrating that there is life in philosophy yet.

Measure
Measure
Evernote helps you remember everything and get organized effortlessly. Download Evernote.

1 comment:

《管锥编》的文献结构——重读张文江《钱锺书传》

《管锥编》的文献结构——重读张文江《钱锺书传》 张治 艺文志eons 在中国现代文化和现代文学相关领域,想完全绕过钱锺书,在今天已经是不可能的了。钱锺书被誉为“文化昆仑”,其著作贯通中西,横跨创作和理论;创作兼及诗文,理论兼及文史哲,以中文论中国,西文论西方,每一方面都取得了独...